Devoir de Philosophie

Broad, Charlie Dunbar

Publié le 22/02/2012

Extrait du document

A Cambridge contemporary of Russell, Moore and Wittgenstein, C.D. Broad wrote on an exceptional range of topics, including causation, perception, the philosophy of space and time, probability and induction, mind and body, ethics and the history of philosophy. He typically set out a number of received positions on a topic, explored their consequences with great clarity, and then came to a cautious estimate of where the truth probably lay. However, Broad made some notable contributions of his own, especially on perception (he defended a representative theory), induction (he argued that our inductive practices require the existence of natural kinds), and time (he argued that tensed facts cannot be analysed away). Although his talents lay in very careful analysis, Broad insisted that there was a proper place in philosophy for metaphysical speculation; he particularly admired McTaggart, and his monumental Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy (1933, 1938) contains some of Broad's best work.

« pseudo-problems, and recommended close attention to our ordinary language as appropriate therapy.

But for Broad, 'in philosophy it is equally silly to be a slave to common speech or to neglect it'.

And he always insisted that there is a proper place not just for Critical Philosophy - 'the analysis and definition of our fundamental concepts, and the clear statement and resolute criticism of our fundamental beliefs' - but also for Speculative Philosophy which hopes 'to reach some general conclusions as to the nature of the Universe, and as to our position and prospects in it'. Much of his writing directly reflects Broad's conception of philosophy: like a judicious scientist, he weighs up the evidence for and against various theories, and then comes to a guarded verdict about their relative acceptability. The final chapter of Mind and Its Place in Nature is an extreme example, where he defines seventeen possible accounts of the relation between the mental and the physical, gradually whittles these down to a short list of three, finally judging one of them - 'emergent materialism' - as 'on all the evidence which is available to me… the most likely view' .

In other hands this approach could make for tedium, but Broad writes with model clarity, and often with admirable elegance enlivened by flashes of mordant wit. 2 Perception Broad discussed perception more often than any other topic.

In particular, Scientific Thought contains a classic development of the sense-datum theory.

When perceiving a stick half immersed in water, it looks bent; and ' the most obvious analysis of the facts is that, when we judge that a straight stick looks bent, we are aware of an object [a 'sensum' , to use Broad's preferred term] which really is bent, and which is related in a peculiarly intimate way to the physically straight stick '.

Broad stresses that there are promising alternatives to this analysis of perceptual experience in terms of the apprehension of some special kind of transitory object.

Still, in Scientific Thought he assumes that the sensum analysis is basically correct, and then explores how it should be developed in detail. This approach has fallen into considerable disfavour since Austin's classic assault on sense-data theories, for example ( Austin, J.L.

§2 ); but it would be wrong to conclude that there can now be nothing of interest in Broad's investigations.

As he remarks in Mind and Its Place in Nature , 'a perceptual situation [such as seeing a cat] is "intuitive", while a thought-situation with the same kind of epistemological object [such as thinking of a cat] is "discursive" '.

Judging my cat is ginger involves thinking of something as being a cat; but one can see a ginger cat without having the concept of a cat at all - the perceptual experience has, to use a later idiom, a non-conceptual content.

And much of Broad's discussion of sensa can be read as an examination of such non-conceptual contents in a framework which need not presuppose that sensa are genuine 'objects' .

For example, he revealingly investigates how our visual experiences interlock with our experiences of bodily movement and touch as we explore the world so as simultaneously to determine the rather different spatial characters of our visual and tactual perceptual contents.. »

↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓

Liens utiles