Devoir de Philosophie

Carolingian renaissance

Publié le 22/02/2012

Extrait du document

The 'Carolingian renaissance' is the name given to the cultural revival in northern Europe during the late eighth and ninth centuries, instigated by Charlemagne and his court scholars. Carolingian intellectual life centred around the recovery of classical Latin texts and learning, though in a strictly Christian setting. The only celebrated philosopher of the time is Johannes Scottus Eriugena, but the daring Neoplatonic speculations of his masterpiece, the Periphyseon (On the Division of Nature) are not at all characteristic of the time and are based on Greek sources (Pseudo-Dionysius, Gregory of Nyssa, Maximus the Confessor) generally unknown to his contemporaries. The mainstream of Carolingian thought is important for the history of philosophy in three particular ways. First, it was at this time that logic first started to take the fundamental role it would have throughout the Middle Ages. Second, scholars began to consider how ideas they found in late antique Latin Neoplatonic texts could be interpreted in a way compatible with Christianity. Third (as would so often again be the case in the Middle Ages), controversies over Christian doctrine led thinkers to analyse some of the concepts they involved: for instance, the dispute in the mid-ninth century over predestination led to discussion about free will and punishment.

« form imitated from Suetonius.

In the mid-ninth century Lupus, Abbot of Ferrières , wrote elegant Latin letters which, in their concern for discovering and collating ancient texts, anticipate the interests of early modern humanists.

Even Greek was studied in this period, especially by scholars of Irish origin such as Martin of Laon, Eriugena and Sedulius Scottus (also a fine Latin poet). Historians often present the role of the Carolingian renaissance in the history of philosophy in terms simply of this rediscovery of ancient texts.

Apart from Eriugena (who is envisaged as an isolated figure, inhabiting the thought world of Greek Neoplatonism or even nineteenth-century German idealism), Carolingian thinkers are described as passive assimilators of the ancient writings they began to study.

Certainly, the forms and techniques favoured by thinkers of the time - excerption, paraphrase, compilation and glossing - give an impression of servility.

Yet, through their particular interests and emphases, Carolingian thinkers set the direction for the subsequent course of medieval philosophy, a direction quite different from what late antique precedent would have suggested.

With the exception of Eriugena, Carolingian thinkers did not take up the Neoplatonic systematizing of the Greek tradition after Plotinus , nor did they reflect the strong emphasis on rhetoric characteristic of classical Latin culture.

Their thought is typified rather by the important place of logic and grammar; by the attempt to reach a Christian interpretation of pagan motifs and philosophical ideas; and by the importance of controversies over Christian doctrine in stimulating argument and analysis. 2 The revival of logic It is no surprise that grammar should have been important in Carolingian education, since Latin was now (even in romance areas) not a mother tongue but a language which needed to be learned.

But it is striking how, even in this period, grammarians went beyond straightforward linguistic instruction to explore some of the semantic problems raised in Priscian's Institutiones grammaticae (Principles of Grammar) .

There was no such obvious didactic reason for the study of logic, yet this subject was central to Carolingian education.

Already in the Libri Carolini , (written very probably by Theodulf of Orleans, circa 789-92), ostentatious use is made of formal logical methods of argument.

In the 790s, Alcuin prefaced a late antique paraphrase of the Categories , which he attributed to Augustine , with a dedicatory verse epistle to Charlemagne: the Categoriae decem (Ten Categories) , as it was called, would be the most widely studied logical text in the next century.

Alcuin also composed a treatise on logic; this was a patchwork of borrowed passages, especially from two late antique Christian encyclopaedists, Cassiodorus and Isidore of Seville ( Encyclopedists, medieval §§6-7 ), and from the Categoriae decem .

Whereas Isidore had treated logic as a verbal art, and both he and Cassiodorus had placed great emphasis on syllogistic argument, Alcuin saw the ten categories as central to the subject, and he used them in understanding the Trinity and in order to distinguish God from his creation.

Alcuin's pupils (especially a fellow Anglo-Saxon, Candidus) continued and extended these interests.

A set of passages (the 'Munich passages' , circa 800) connected with. »

↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓

Liens utiles